Leaving the Limelight, Entering the Mystery

Engaging Narrative Anagogically

By Noah R. Karger

In an age obsessed with narrative, what we need is not a return to a more critical Enlightenment hermeneutic, but instead, the anagogic—a return to mystery.

Growing up in Evangelical churches, I was frequently asked to share my testimony, the condensed, narrativized version of how I became a Christian. I hated this question because I didn’t have a good testimony. The recipe for a good testimony is: (1) some kind of “fall from grace”—drug addiction, porn obsession, overt atheism—(2) a subsequent “come to Jesus” experience, and, finally, (3) a complete, overnight life transformation. One time a pastor instructed me to give the “thirty second version,” to which I replied, “I don’t know if I have one.” He countered: “Everyone has one. You just need to find it.”

We are obsessed with narrative, something literary theorist Peter Brooks addresses in his most recent book, Seduced by Story: The Use and Abuse of Narrative. Brooks argues that this fixation has resulted in a “storification of reality,” undermining our ability to distinguish fact from fiction. We are in danger, he says, of “asserting the dominion of our constructed realities over the real thing.”

While Brooks largely attributes this storification to the proliferation of certain themes in the novel, in their reviews of his book, Caterina Domeneghini and Sophia Stewart both argue that it probably has more to do with our digital era. For instance, social media prompts us to make stories out of our own lives, suggesting that they should present as novel, organized, and readily accessible packages of meaning. In an entertainment-obsessed world, we compete for the dwindling attention of our peers—or followers—at every turn. Joan Didion famously opens her essay “The White Album” by remarking that, “We tell ourselves stories in order to live.” But what’s more, says Stewart, “we’re also turning ourselves into stories in order to live.”

Brooks posits that, among other things, narrative seems “nearly always to be bound up with questions of knowing,” and is, thus, “a cognitive instrument.” He cites historian Hayden White, who demonstrates that narrative’s etymology can be traced back to the Sanskrit root gnâ, “know.” If stories are a cognitive instrument, what kind of knowledge do they permit us? Though they have long served an interpersonal function—a way to communicate shared religious and cultural values—they now increasingly serve a primarily intrapersonal one. Today, we see narrative as a vehicle for both defining the self and motivating it to fuller actualization.

Social media prompts us to make stories out of our own lives.

Take, for instance, “main character energy,” the social media trend that promotes seeing yourself as the protagonist of your own life. It is especially interesting, notes Kyle Chayka, that this trend has taken off in the wake of pandemic-induced self-isolation, almost as a response to the lack of control—an effort to “exert ourselves upon the world” again. One main-character-energy advocate claims that “TikTok and social media has made it more attainable for you to write your own story.”

Spotify capitalized on this movement, frequently updating a playlist called “my life is a movie,” which has nearly 2 million followers and counting. After all, who wouldn’t want a little “Everybody Wants to Rule the World” while walking around campus or dancing alone in Central Park or staring out the window of a bus? “Welcome to your life,” which, in the case of one TikToker, involved buying a plane ticket to Miami just to visit her favorite thrift store, all after deciding one morning: “It’s time for me to start acting like I’m a main character.” She reassures her followers, “I know I’m not, but sometimes it’s fun to pretend.”

This internalizing of narrative is also evident in the rise of Jordan Peterson, the internet’s most polarizing self-help guru. Aside from his political opinions, Peterson became famous for convincing people that the hero’s journey should inform their own lives, primarily via his obsession with Pinocchio and the Bible (which apparently have a lot to say to each other). His most popular YouTube series is on “the psychological significance” of the book of Genesis, the videos having almost 50 million views combined. In an increasingly secular society, anytime religious literature gets that much (positive) attention without the endorsement of a religious organization, something’s up.

Peterson opens the first talk of his series by confronting the elephant in the room: “Why bother with this strange, old book at all?” Throughout the series, Peterson guides the audience to his answer, arguing that “this strange, old book” is a story that can help us make sense of our own. Analyzing God’s call to Abraham in Genesis 12:1-3, he says, “If you leave your country and your kin and your father’s house and you go out into a land that your intuition guides you to, you’re going to undergo these radical transformations… and that’s the same as the dragon fight—that’s the hero’s story.” He speaks like this for two and a half hours without intermission, a packed auditorium of college students hanging on his every word. This is an impressive feat, and evidence that story construed in this way is commensurate with our zeitgeist. Today, narrative is turning us inward more often than out.

Narrative is turning us inward more often than out. 

Peterson’s wildly popular interpretation of the Bible reveals what happens when this main character hermeneutic dictates our engagement with story—or perhaps the other way around. In her incisive analysis, Dani Treweek commends Peterson for his profound interest in “the human story,” but notes that this interest is, most specifically, in “the human story.” To Peterson, the story of Abraham is about self-optimization via adventure. And yet, Treweek explains, in reality, it isn’t about that all—none of Scripture is. It’s about “the eternal glorification of the Son of Man.” The Son of Man who knew nothing of self-optimization “but emptied himself, taking the form of a slave,” becoming “obedient to the point of death—even death on a cross.”

Our problem is not an obsession with story, but the function we think it serves—self-optimization—and the consequent self-focused hermeneutic we employ to engage it. We are consumed with creating, revising, and telling our own story; we insist on seeing our lives as mini narratives—what philosopher Galen Strawson has coined his “Psychological Narrativity Thesis.”

Reminiscent of Didion, Brooks further posits that “we have fictions in order not to die of the forlornness of our condition in the world.” He suggests that story forms the basis of our interaction with the world but, in doing so, reduces it to a “form of play.” He here adopts pediatrician and psychoanalyst D.W. Winnicott’s construal of “play,” that is, the infant’s original “negotiation between subject and objective world.” In this, the infant learns to imbue “transitional objects” (stuffed animals, toys, etc.) with illusory value and thereby “obtain a sense of mastery over things.” Brooks argues that stories function like this, as well, and are therefore valuable not insofar as they are true but only insofar as they are useful (a prioritization which is very much in line with Peterson’s pragmatism). Without such imaginative play, he claims, “we risk being overwhelmed by an inhuman world.” In other words, all that stands between us and our erasure is the occasional suspension of disbelief.

I’d like to suggest the opposite, that our humanity is held together not by pretense—and our ability to stomach it from time to time—but by truth: stories which do not mischievously play on our capacity to believe but invite its full, authentic participation. That’s because our stories—our solipsistic “main character” constructions—do not form the basis of story but rather signal our privation. Narrative does not originate in the playful “negotiation between subject and objective world,” but in God’s creating both, and in their reconciliation in Christ.

Brooks seeks to come to the aid of a humanity consumed by myth, but in doing so, he makes the same mistake which spawned the very problem he diagnoses. Attempting to return story to its “proper” epistemological place, he reduces it to child’s play, asserting over it the dominance of rational scrutiny. He is not the first to do so. For this was the work of what Nietzsche called “Socratism.” Beginning with Socrates himself, Nietzsche argued, the movement resulted in an age “bent on the destruction of myth.” But it was this belittling of myth that birthed Nietzsche, and with Nietzsche, a progeny of aspiring Übermenschen “main characters.”

Myth has made a comeback so robust that we are not now discussing its destruction, but the storification of our age. The Nietzschean variety of myth, specifically, is identified by Henri de Lubac as deliberately barbaric and self-idolizing. It does not lead us into the fruits of our humanity but locates us “back among the beasts.” Both Socratism’s rejection of myth and the Nietzschean appropriation of it leave us with cultures that cannot rightly engage narrative, that cannot tell the truth. It is Nietzschean myth—and not myth itself—that has resulted in our age of information disorder. While Stewart is right that “a more critically minded and media-literate populace” would be of use in setting this to rights, it is not “the only antidote.” In fact, it is not an antidote at all, but is only useful in service to the actual antidote: the mystery of Christ, the one and true story.

As de Lubac articulates, “there is no more disastrous illusion than” that of Socratism (and Brooks): “this victory over illusion.” Reducing narrative to a “useful” form of “play,” to a fictional imposition on a disjointed string of events—this is no cure for a storified world. What we need is not de-mystification of myth but, in fact, the opposite. We need myth to be properly situated in mystery once more. Only then can its epistemic function be restored.

“What can it be but that we have lost the breast that fed us, we have lost Myth?” Nietzsche asks. And today, as we overcorrect in the other direction, what can it be but that we have lost the breast that fed myth, we have lost mystery? This, as it did to Nietzsche, has caused us to become self-involved in our mythologizing. We have taken after Nietzsche’s hyperbolic self-affirmation, on display in his Ecce Homo (including works such as “Why I am so Wise” and “Why I am so Clever”). Myth sans mystery, says de Lubac, “links us with nature… but also enslaves us to her fatal powers.” This “pagan myth” is utterly unchristian in that it takes as its blueprint one’s own image, a form of idolatry. What we need is not our own image, but a “chaste and sober rapture of the Spirit.”

We are not to orient ourselves as the protagonist of our own story, but as a participant in the creative work of God.

And so, we are not to orient ourselves as the protagonist of our own story, but as a participant in the creative work of God—a servant. When we read of Abraham being called out of Ur, we aren’t to read it as a myth about self-transformation because, as Treweek notes, the story isn’t even about Abraham. Rather, it is about God’s covenantal faithfulness and love for humanity. Unlike in Peterson’s reading, Kierkegaard proposes that Abraham acts beyond the universalizable myth, and thus he stands only to be judged by God. He is “therefore at no instant a tragic hero,” and in the case of his journey up Mount Moriah, is “either a murderer or a believer.” Our lives, like that of Abraham, are not by themselves stories but are lived in response to one—and in that way become mysteriously part of one.

Because story is more than a solipsistic game, having an actual objective basis beyond the psyche, it requires a different hermeneutic—one that doesn’t turn us further into ourselves, but opens us up to the world. We need a framework that allows us to step outside of our narrativizing and into the narrative, to operate in faith. Moreover, while for Nietzsche, “‘knowledge’ is a referring back,” for the Christian, knowledge is a looking forward. Thus, our foundation must also invite us to look ahead, to hope. This hermeneutic of faith and hope is the anagogic.

Hugh of Saint Victor differentiates allegory from anagoge by noting that, while allegory denotes an invisible fact symbolized or represented by a visible one, anagoge is a “sursum ductio” (reasoning upwards)—an invisible fact revealed by a visible one. This reasoning upwards is a mystical approach to knowledge; it’s an ecstatic encounter—from the Greek ekstasis, meaning “outside of oneself.” While the self-discovery hermeneutic takes one’s own personality as its object, moves us into ourselves, and produces restlessness, the anagogic orients to God and thereby to neighbor, moving us outside of ourselves, stirring up faith and hope. Thus, in interpreting narrative, the anagogic befits the climax of all story, the person of Christ. Like Christ, we become capacious for sacrifice, opened to the world, full of life.

Anagoge draws the reader not into themselves but into the incarnation and its eschatological import, pointing to the resurrection of the dead and the life everlasting. It invites hope—a hope that does not escape present realities but discovers the object of its expectation in and through them. In ascending the ladder of detail and data to arrive at a thing’s eternal import, the anagogic does not overlook or denounce the particularities of a story. Rather, it pervades—and thereby elevates—them. Essentially, it invites resurrection.

This method of scriptural interpretation—like the literal, moral, and allegorical—need not be reserved for Scripture alone. Instead, it ought to shape the way we read all stories and, beyond that, the way we observe life. Flannery O’Connor, for instance, felt it the appropriate approach to the reading and writing of her work. She describes it as “see[ing] multiple levels of reality in one image or one situation.” While Nietzsche argued that the capacity for myth is what gives us our power of creativity, for O’Connor, it was, more basically, mystery. Those familiar with her work can attest to this. It’s the kind of experience you can’t put a finger on, the kind you can’t dissect or even digest. In a way, it swallows you.

The task of storytelling is not to manufacture but to see narrative, to discover what is true and beautiful by noticing its presence in the mundane and mysterious alike.

The anagogic does not fabricate illusions but engages through the literal meaning. Dante explained that the literal should always precede the anagogic, as it is “the sense in whose meaning the others are enclosed.” Or, as O’Connor puts it, fiction ought to “embody mystery through manners”—through the very concrete details which comprise our existence. The anagogic does not seek meaning in the mundane just to move past it, but seeks meaning there because it desires to dwell, like Christ, in all its corporeality. In suffusing the details of daily living with the mysteries of Christ, we become more alive.

Therefore, stories engaged anagogically fall outside of Didion’s definition: “the imposition of a narrative line upon disparate images… the ‘ideas’ with which we have learned to freeze the shifting phantasmagoria which is our actual experience.” Phantasmagoria comes from the Greek phántasma (by way of the French, fantasmagorie), denoting a ghost, an apparition, a dream. Yet, in its proper form, storytelling is not the work of imposing chimerical fictions on a disjointed series of events. Rather, it is the work of seeing through these events to the meaning from which they flow.

This is why O’Connor said she was “always irritated by people who imply that writing fiction is an escape from reality. It is a plunge into reality and it’s very shocking to the system.” The task of storytelling is not to manufacture but to see narrative, to discover what is true and beautiful by noticing its presence in the mundane and mysterious alike. Seeing rightly, the stories we tell become contextualized in that of Christ.

Watching Jesus walk atop the sea, the disciples cried, “Phántasma estin!” (It is a ghost!). It is no wonder, then, that we make the same error. It is no wonder that, peering into the deep well of narrative, we come up with little more than our own reflection, a phántasma of story itself. Engaging narrative anagogically, the apparent “shifting phantasmagoria” of our lives proves to be otherwise.

A taxonomy of story commonly attributed to Tolstoy goes like this: “All great literature is one of two stories; a man goes on a journey or a stranger comes to town.” This man is Christ, who journeys to the cross; he is a stranger to his own, come down from heaven. Learning to discover story on its proper axis, we are liberated from the phántasmas of our anxiety-ridden self-involvement. We are invited to stand outside of ourselves, outside of our vanishing ten-second stories and inside the eternal story of a God who sent his Only Begotten Son. We are invited into a life of faith.

To put it another way, for G.K. Chesterton, the epistemic purpose of fictional stories is to remind us of the beauty and wonder of real stories. They “make rivers run with wine only to make us remember, for one wild moment, that they run with water.” They serve not to augment an abysmal reality, but to remind us of a wonderful reality: Christ. By anagogically engaging fiction and fact alike, we are liberated from our Truman Show-esque prisons and into a life of resurrection. The question becomes not whether I can craft a sensational thirty-second testimony, but how a thirty-second myth will birth its accompanying mystery. May we be, as de Lubac pleads, “more at pains to live by the mystery than eager to defend its formulas.” For it is the mystery of our God in whose company alone everything is made to run with wine.

Illustrations by Sarah Clark

Noah R. Karger is an MDiv student at Gordon-Conwell Theological Seminary and a research assistant at the Center for the Study of Global Christianity. You can reach him at noahkarger.com.